WWW.ABSTRACT.DISLIB.INFO
FREE ELECTRONIC LIBRARY - Abstracts, online materials
 
<< HOME
CONTACTS



Pages:   || 2 | 3 |

«1.Magnitude Estimation of disfluency by stutterers and nonstutterers. Melanie Russell,1 Martin Corley,2 and Robin Lickley1 Speech and Language ...»

-- [ Page 1 ] --

1.Magnitude Estimation of disfluency by stutterers and

nonstutterers.

Melanie Russell,1 Martin Corley,2 and Robin Lickley1

Speech and Language Sciences

Queen Margaret University College

Edinburgh

EH12 8TS

sp1russ@student.qmuc.ac.uk, rlickley@qmuc.ac.uk

School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences

University of Edinburgh

Edinburgh

EH8 9JZ

Martin.Corley@ed.ac.uk

1.Author Note

The order of the second and third authors is arbitrary. Correspondence concerning this chapter should be addressed to either Martin Corley or Robin Lickley.

2.Summary Everyone produces disfluencies when they speak spontaneously. However, whereas most disfluencies pass unnoticed, the repetitions, blocks and prolongations produced by stutterers can have a severely disruptive effect on communication. The causes of stuttering have proven hard to pin down - researchers differ widely in their views on the cognitive mechanisms that underlie it. The present chapter presents initial research which supports a view (Vasic and Wijnen, this volume) that places the emphasis firmly on the self-monitoring system, suggesting that stuttering may be a consequence of over-sensitivity to the types of minor speech error that we all make.

Our study also allows us to ask whether the speech of people who stutter is perceived as qualitatively different from that of nonstutterers, when it is fluent and when it contains similar types of minor disfluencies. Our results suggest that for closely matched, naturally occurring segments of speech, listeners rate the speech of stutterers as more disfluent than that of nonstutterers.

3.Introduction Research into stuttering often seems to fall at the first hurdle: that of defining what constitutes a stutter, in contrast to the disfluent speech that everyone produces. As of yet there is no consensus on a formal definition: researchers such as Perkins (1995) emphasise the speaker's feelings of loss of control; others, such as Postma and Kolk (1993), prefer definitions in terms of the frequencies of particular types of disfluency.

However, a consensus is slowly emerging that some of the symptoms associated with stuttering can be accounted for within a model of speech developed to account for normal hesitations, speech errors, and self-corrections (e.g., Levelt, 1983).

In this chapter, we provide initial evidence that stutterers appear to be oversensitive when assessing disfluencies common to both nonstuttering and stuttering speakers.

Our research supports a view (Vasic and Wijnen, this volume) which emphasises the role of self-monitoring in the production of stuttered speech.

1.Self-monitoring in stuttering

Self-monitoring can be described as “the process of inspecting one’s own speech and taking appropriate action when errors are made” (Hartsuiker & Kolk, 2001). Levelt’s (1983, 1989) theory assumes that both overt speech and an internal speech plan are monitored. Postma (2000) summarises a number of common speech errors and identifies evidence for two types of self-monitoring: overt speech repairs (where speakers correct themselves mid-utterance) support the monitoring of external speech, whereas covert repairs (where there is no overt error, but a repair can be inferred from a hesitation in the speech output) supply evidence for the internal monitor. In fact, evidence suggests that the repair is often ready before the error is articulated (e.g., Blackmer & Mitton, 1991), and that errors can be made in the absence of articulatory activities or spoken output (for example, when imagining that one is articulating a tongue-twister: Dell & Repka, 1992). Thus the self-monitoring system would appear to have components which are distinct from the monitoring of motor systems (such as articulation) and from the auditory channel. Importantly, the speech that we produce has already been affected by self-monitoring; there is no external record of the original, possibly imperfect, speech plan.

Recent theorists have taken this view on board. For example, Postma & Kolk (1993) hypothesise that stuttering results from covert detection and correction of errors in the articulatory plan through the internal self-monitor. Covert self-correction would prevent the speech error from becoming overt, but would, as a side-effect, compromise the fluency of speech. Evidence for this Covert Repair Hypothesis is inconclusive (for details see: Hartsuiker, Kolk and Lickley, this volume; Vasic and Wijnen, this volume), but still supported by current studies (e.g. Melnicke, Conture and Ohde, this volume, who suggest that not only phonological encoding, but syntactic and semantic processes may be impaired in the formulation of speech by children who stutter).

Blackmer and Mitton (1991) also ascribe a role to monitoring. According to these authors, rapid subsyllabic repetitions, a key symptom of stuttering, occur when the monitor detects a lack of input, and consequently ‘restarts’ previous articulatory movements.

More recently, Wijnen (2000; Vasic & Wijnen, this volume) has placed the emphasis entirely on the self-monitoring system, by proposing that stuttering is the direct result of an overvigilant monitor. Paradoxically, the repairs made often introduce disfluencies rather than prevent them: “stutterers stutter because they try to avoid it” (Wijnen, 2000). Such a view can be easily extended to account for aspects of stuttering such as context-dependency and linguistic distribution.





These proposals have in common the assumption that stuttering is related to selfmonitoring; they also share, to a greater or lesser degree, the entailment that there is a continuity between stuttered and normal disfluencies (in contrast to, e.g., Perkins, 1995). Arguably, the most parsimonious view is that of Vasic and Wijnen (this volume); since there are no differences in planning processes (Postma & Kolk, 1993) or timings (Blackmer & Mitton, 1991) between stutterers and nonstutterers, all differences between the two groups must be attributed to the self-monitor. Given an appropriate experimental paradigm, we should be able to find direct evidence for the self-monitor’s sensitivity in those who stutter. By a similar process of inference, we

would expect there to be continuity between the speech of stutterers and nonstutterers:

it is not errors in planned speech, but how many repairs are initiated, which differentiates the two groups.

2.Sensitivity of the self-monitor

According to Vasic and Wijnen, there are three specific ways in which the speech monitor may be ‘over-sensitive’ to (potential) speech errors. Firstly, too much cognitive effort may be invested in monitoring. Secondly, the focus (as distinct from effort) of the monitoring system may be rigid and unadaptive. Thirdly, the threshold of the monitor may be too low: a ‘hypersensitivity’ to minor speech distortions that non-stutterers would tolerate (or in other words regard as within the bounds of ‘normal’ speech) increases the likelihood of stuttering. The first two assertions are addressed in Vasic and Wijnen’s chapter; in this chapter we focus on the third.

There are three basic proposals for the nature of the self-monitoring system. The first (Levelt, 1983, 1989) supposes that the mechanisms (at the conceptual, phonetic, and auditory levels) which understand language produced by others are shared with the self-monitoring system. The second (Laver, 1973, 1980) assumes multiple monitoring devices attuned specifically to production, including the potential to monitor the articulatory motor processes themselves. A third view (MacKay, 1987, 1992a,b) suggests that error awareness arises from the prolonged activation of otherwise uncomitted nodes in the system for speech production. In an extensive review, Postma (2000) concludes that current evidence largely favours the view of Levelt (1983, 1989) in which the systems responsible for language perception and for self-monitoring are shared. If we accept this view, then people who stutter should show increased sensitivity to disfluencies in others’, as well as their own, speech. In the simplest case, this sensitivity would be manifest whatever the provenance of the disfluent speech -- i.e., whether it is uttered by a stutterer or a nonstutterer.

The current study addresses this issue by eliciting, from a group of stutterers and a comparison group of non-stutterers, ratings of the ‘severity of disfluency’ of recorded speech fragments. The fragments are excerpted from recordings made of dialogues between pairs of stutterers, and between matched pairs of nonstutterers. This allows us to simultaneously address the second, continuity, assumption of many singlemodel accounts. Few studies have directly assessed the sensitivity of people who stutter to dysfluency in the speech of others. Postma and Kolk (1992) come close, by comparing the abilities of people who stutter and fluent subjects to detect errors (rather than disfluencies) in sequences of CV and VC syllables produced by another speaker. Their finding was that people who stutter were less successful than controls in detecting errors under these conditions. In addition, they found that the two groups did not differ in their ability to detect their own errors in the production of CV and VC sequences. The results are taken as evidence that self-monitoring via auditory feedback is not impaired in people who stutter. In our study, we ask listeners to rate severity of dysfluency, rather than error, in samples of spontaneous speech, rather than non-word strings.

3.Continuity between stuttered and normal disfluencies

To some researchers (e.g. Bloodstein, 1970), the difference between the clinical disorder of stuttering, and “normal” speech disfluency is simply a matter of degree.

Stuttering is recognised by the frequency and severity of syllable-sound repetition.

“There is no test for determining the precise point at which speech repetitions stop being ‘normal’ and become ‘stuttering’. We cannot specify where the wall of an igloo ends and the roof begins. It is not a scientific question” (Bloodstein, 1970). In order to strengthen his argument, Bloodstein (1970) describes what he calls the “Consistency Effect”: the distribution of disfluencies in the speech sequence is supposedly similar for stutterers and nonstutterers. Cross (n.d.) agrees that a categorical differentiation between stutterers and nonstutterers is both unnecessary and invalid, because the nature and degree of the problem vary from one individual to the next. He concludes that the issue is not whether the person is a stutterer or not, but whether the form or frequency of speech disruptions interferes with their ability to convey a message.

However, Perkins (1990) insists that a qualitative categorical distinction does exist between stutterers’ and nonstutterers’ speech. He suggests that there are two definitions of stuttering. The observer’s viewpoint corresponds to the continuity hypothesis, whereas the stutterer’s viewpoint corresponds to a categorical judgement.

According to this perspective, speakers know when they stutter, but listeners can only guess. So, disfluency in nonstutterers is concerned with the motor control aspects of speech, whereas disfluency in stutterers seems to involve additional psychological aspects such as loss of control and feelings of helplessness.

In order to disentangle these views, the current study obtains ratings of fluent and disfluent speech fragments recorded from dialogues between stutterers and between nonstutterers. We should be able to ascertain whether there is a general distinction to be made between stutterers’ and nonstutterers’ speech, and (based on Levelt’s, 1983, view of self-monitoring outlined above) whether stutterers perceive a discontinuity where others perceive a continuum.

4.The Present Study

The present pilot study investigates the phenomenon of stuttering perceptually, in contrast to previous work (e.g., Vasic & Wijnen, this volume) which has posited selfmonitoring accounts of stutterers’ speech production. In the experiment reported in this chapter, we asked judges who stuttered to rate the fluency or otherwise of short extracts from recordings made in naturalistic circumstances of dialogues between pairs of stuttering participants or pairs of nonstuttering controls. For each type of dialogue, half of the extracts were of fluent speech, and half were of mildly disfluent speech, where the onset of a word was repeated a single time. We would not expect either set of judges to rate extracts obtained from dialogues between stutterers as more disfluent overall than those obtained from nonstutterers’ dialogues; we expect there to be little or no qualitative difference between the speech of the two groups. However, to test Vasic and Wijnen's hypothesis directly, the ratings given by our judges were compared with those from a second group of judges without stutters. If Vasic and Wijnen are correct, the judges who stutter should be more sensitive to disfluency.

This sensitivity could manifest itself in one of two ways: if the judges who stutter detect and are sensitive to minor infelicities in the fluent speech extracts, we might expect them to rate these (as well as the disfluent samples) as worse. On the other hand, an increased sensitivity to disfluency may make people who stutter likely to differentiate more between fluent and disfluent speech.

There are two justifications for the approach taken here: firstly, we avoid prejudging whether disfluent speech should be considered as ‘normal’ or ‘stuttered’, an absolute distinction which many researchers dispute; and secondly, if we accept Levelt’s view that the processes responsible for self-monitoring are also responsible for the processing of others’ speech, we are in a position to directly compare the sensitivities of stutterers and nonstutterers to disfluencies in speech. The approach relies on using a rating system which is sensitive enough to capture small differences in listeners’ perceptions of the fluency of recorded speech. We have chosen to use Magnitude Estimation, an approach used increasingly in linguistic studies where fine judgements are required, which we outline below.

5.Magnitude Estimation



Pages:   || 2 | 3 |


Similar works:

«Family Law Summit Brisbane 8 June 2011 Paul Fildes Taussig Cherrie Fildes KEYNOTE: Outlook for Family Law Practitioners in 2011-12 1. EMERGING TRENDS IN PARENTING CASES A) ALIENATION AND ENMESHMENT Parental Alienation Definition A child's campaign of denigration against a parent that results from 'programming' or 'brainwashing' of the child by the other parent. Background An American psychiatrist, with no background in child abuse, Richard Gardner, propounded the parental alienation syndrome...»

«myself as a delicious peach I was balancing on the curb, having sex. Pretending. In my mind, I was doing it. Oh, baby, I said. Even to me oh baby sounded stupid. My dad was always late. My brother said they weren’t visitation rights, they were visitation wrongs. My brother was having nothing to do with “el traitor.” My mother sent me down to the corner for Dad to pick me up. “I don’t need the man in my driveway,” she said. She was very against sex. She said things like why buy the...»

«CHANGING CHOPIN: POSTHUMOUS VARIANTS AND PERFORMANCE APPROACHES By Ho Sze-Hwei Grace A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Master of Philosophy Department of Music University of Birmingham Birmingham, United Kingdom September 2012 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of...»

«Modelling reductions of pollutant loads due to improved management practices in the Great Barrier Reef catchments Burnett Mary NRM region Technical Report Volume 7 Prepared by Contact Bantigegne Fentie Bantigegne Fentie Department of Science Information Technology Innovation and Arts, Senior Scientist (Modelling) Brisbane Email: Banti.Fentie@qld.gov.au © State of Queensland (DSITIA) 2014 Phone: (07) 3170 5628 Ownership of intellectual property rights Unless otherwise noted, copyright (and any...»

«3 Pavlovian conditioning: reflexes, expectancies and involuntary emotional associations The development of Pavlov’s experimental method of producing conditioned salivation in dogs was described in chapter 1, and a discussion of Pavlov’s application of his findings to the problems of human psychology will be found in chapter 6. Here I intend to give an up-to-date account of a selection of experiments and theories in the area, which has come to be known as classical conditioning. The...»

«GEODON® (ziprasidone HCl) Capsules GEODON® (ziprasidone mesylate) for Injection FOR IM USE ONLY WARNING Increased Mortality in Elderly Patients with Dementia-Related Psychosis— Elderly patients with dementia-related psychosis treated with antipsychotic drugs are at an increased risk of death. Analyses of seventeen placebo-controlled trials (modal duration of 10 weeks), largely in patients taking atypical antipsychotic drugs, revealed a risk of death in drugtreated patients of between 1.6 to...»

«Volume 34INumber 3IJuly 2OI2IPages 240-253 Strong Mindfulness: Integrating Mindfulness and Character Strengths Ryan M. Niemiec Tayyab Rashid Marcello Spinella This article explores the integration of mindfulness meditation and character strengths. Beyond simply focusing attention, mindfulness involves the cultivation ofattention infused by an unconditional friendliness and interest Universally valued character strengths (Peterson ó Seligman, 2004) are useful cotistructs for such an infusion....»

«LEARNING THEORIES BEHAVIORISM CHAPTER 4 l 4 Learning Theories Behaviorism CHAPTER LE ARNI NG OUTCOMES After studying this chapter, you should be able to: 1. Explain the principles of classical conditioning, operant conditioning and social learning theory;2. Compare among classical conditioning, operant conditioning and social learning theory; and 3. Apply the principles of classical conditioning, operant conditioning and social learning theory in classroom teaching. CHAPTER 4 LEARNING THEORIES...»

«Dear Parents, guardians and friends of Xavier College, Remember the good old days when happiness was a picnic lunch down at the l ipa beach – then came skin cancer – or a great feed of Darrell Lea‘s Rocky Road – c n Pri then came obesity! Now we have to read books with titles like ―Authentic the Happiness Using the New Positive Psychology to Realise Your Potential for m Lasting Fulfilment‖! Or do we? Maybe we can still rely on good old-fashioned Fro things like: ―Finding fun in...»

«Modelling a receiver’s position to persuasive arguments Hien Nguyen, Judith Masthoff, and Peter Edwards University of Aberdeen {hnguyen,jmasthoff,pedwards}@csd.abdn.ac.uk Social psychology shows that the effect of a persuasive argument depends on characteristics of the person to be persuaded, including the person’s involvement with the topic and the discrepancy between the person’s current position on the topic and the argument’s position. Via a series of experiments, this paper...»

«Factsheet – Domestic violence June 2016 This Factsheet does not bind the Court and is not exhaustive Domestic violence “. [T]he issue of domestic violence, which can take various forms ranging from physical to psychological violence or verbal abuse. is a general problem which concerns all member States and which does not always surface since it often takes place within personal relationships or closed circuits and it is not only women who are affected. The [European] Court [of Human...»

«Panpsychism and Panprotopsychism1 David J. Chalmers 1 Introduction Panpsychism, taken literally, is the doctrine that everything has a mind. In practice, people who call themselves panpsychists are not committed to as strong a doctrine. They are not committed to the thesis that the number two has a mind, or that the Eiffel tower has a mind, or that the city of Canberra has a mind, even if they believe in the existence of numbers, towers, and cities. Instead, we can understand panpsychism as the...»





 
<<  HOME   |    CONTACTS
2017 www.abstract.dislib.info - Abstracts, online materials

Materials of this site are available for review, all rights belong to their respective owners.
If you do not agree with the fact that your material is placed on this site, please, email us, we will within 1-2 business days delete him.